Philosophy

Marx and Universal Human Rights

Libertarian or democratic socialists - in contrast to more authoritarian members of the socialist tradition - tend to preserve and maintain their philosophical links to more mainstream liberal beliefs, and represent their political program [correctly] as an evolution or perfection of the clearly flawed and self-serving modern liberal democratic state. Among the liberal values that socialists defend are the fundamental so-called human rights - political, civic, social, economic and cultural. A society that truly guaranteed all the rights identified in that tradition to would not only be normatively desirable, but in all likelihood have a radically re-imagined political and economic structure. I am of course guilty myself of this philosophical borrowing, writing at length about the desirability of orienting radical politics around ‘fundamental rights’ in my first book, “Politics for the New Dark Age: Staying Positive Amidst Disorder”.

In Chapter 12 of my second book, “Evolutionary Politics: Socialism for Social Species” [Available Now!], I endorse what is broadly known as the ’social theory’ of rights.

“We cannot therefore speak of the ‘natural rights’ of individuals as the early liberal philosophers did. A person alone in a state of nature has no claims to make on another, and therefore no claims by others to be protected against. All norms are social norms and all rights are social rights.”

In other words, my position on rights is that they are dialectical - worked out through social relationships, and in many respects constitutive of interpersonal relationships in societies delineated by that kind of symbolic legal norm. All laws, norms and institutions are strategic solutions to the problems of group life, and as such these norms evolve in a historically contingent way in response to the material conditions of the group. A necessary corollary of the social theory of rights is that the content and scope of rights can vary depending on the social context - different populations with different structures or facing different problems may understand rights differently, as liberal societies of course did at different historical stages of their own development. For many advocates of a rights-based approach to philosophy, law and morality, the social theory of rights is unacceptable precisely because it means ‘human rights’ are not truly human rights because the benefits and privileges attaching to those claim vary by place, time and culture - what we have instead are the rights of Americans, Chinese citizens, Ugandan citizens and so on.

The social theory of rights is juxtaposed in the literature against several alternative theories, the first and foremost of which are natural law theories. The natural law tradition states that rights are observable features of the universe, which the modern liberal democratic state has merely discovered and codified through the use of “capital-R Reason”, or through its unique historical experiences, or as a result of its unique history, culture or traditions etc. The natural law tradition has its origins in religious belief - “all men are created equal” - but does not require a specific spiritual belief to be true. Natural rights are laws of the universe since, as Spinoza believed, a creator deity could not create natural laws that were contrary to Reason - nor could any rational sovereign.

The alternative, that we liberal humanists in law school used to frown upon, is the legal positivist school, which argues that rights are not observable features of the universe, but rather contingent grants of privileges by legal authorities. In other words, human rights as we know them today did not exist before the Universal Declaration of Human Rights was written (which is unenforceable anyway), and the only rights an individual may claim are those that are enforceable through the legal and executive arms of a particular state. Whether we regard this cynical view positively (as conservatives do) or negatively (as most Marxists and social critics do), it’s hard to argue that it’s at least trivially true - the rights we think we have today are specific legal entitlements that were granted by specific sovereign authorities under specific historical circumstances. For a traditionalist, what gives human rights their power is that they were granted by righteous authorities and have stood the test of time in the face of subsequent historical events.

Materialism and Liberalism

Let’s presume for a moment that universal human rights are a desirable ethical good. It’s trivially true that a resident of Mogadishu, Somalia does not enjoy the same degree of protection of their right to life as a citizen of Canberra, Australia; it’s trivially true that the material capacity of a Western European state to guarantee a basic standard of living, good quality healthcare and education, and a right to housing, is dramatically better than the capacity of Sierra Leone or the Solomon Islands. Yet of course, as humanists and egalitarians, we want the citizens of Mogadishu, Freetown and Honiara to enjoy the same standard of human rights as ourselves. In Leninism there’s a concept of “the transformation of quantity into quality”. In other words, a material leap forward, or leap backwards, can be so significant as to categorically change the classification of an object, process or social relation. From a human rights perspective, it’s clear that a relative deprivation of rights can be so severe that we would no long recognise that an individual was having their rights - and thus their equal dignity as a member of our species - respected at all.

Marxism is a materialist philosophy. We do not begin from the supposition of abstract principles about the nature of human life and deduce our political beliefs from these idealist abstractions, but instead are interested first and foremost in social conditions as they actually are. In many instances, this allows us to see the good work that has been done by the bourgeois revolutions - but not be so blinded by their philosophical commitments that we can’t criticise them. Socialists are somewhat less prone than liberals to the disappointment of theory not matching reality. Marx was of course correct when he cynically observed that liberal rights were first and foremost bourgeois rights - to negative liberty, property and security of the individual against the state - but we need not give in to such cynicism and reject the idea of universal human rights in their entirety, as many historical communists did.

“None of the so-called rights of man, therefore, go beyond egoistic man, beyond man as a member of civil society – that is, an individual withdrawn into himself, into the confines of his private interests and private caprice, and separated from the community. In the rights of man, he is far from being conceived as a species-being; on the contrary, species-life itself, society, appears as a framework external to the individuals, as a restriction of their original independence. The sole bond holding them together is natural necessity, need and private interest, the preservation of their property and their egoistic selves.”

I’ve discussed Marx’s concept of ‘species-being’ or ‘Gattungswesen’ in an earlier blog, but to quickly summarise, the Marxist theory of human nature begins and ends with his or her existence as a material being. The fact that human beings share common needs - food clothing, shelter, health, education, culture - creates a common ‘human nature’. “The universality of man appears in practice precisely in the universality which makes all nature his inorganic body – both inasmuch as nature is his direct means of life, and the material, the object, and the instrument of his life activity.” In process philosophy such as Marxism, the essence of an object is defined by its relationships (not the other way round, as in classical metaphysics) as a result human nature is defined by the totality of human social and material relationships.

Thus, from the concept of species-being, it it relatively straightforward to recover the universality of human rights from a Marxist framework. Rights are those material needs which are necessary for the full development of the human individual, and which the individual cannot guarantee through their own powers such that they enter into social relationships and constructs in order to secure them. And while a society’s ability to secure fundamental rights may vary by material circumstances, our shared biological and cultural inheritance as humans means we have much more in common than we differ from one another. Both Marxists and universalist liberals would look equally aghast at the argument of some pro-state or pro-capitalist developmentalists that, actually, the citizens of Mogadishu, Freetown or Honiara don’t need as much food, shelter or healthcare as citizens of the West.

Class and Dialectics

One of the fundamental misunderstandings of both critics of socialism and vulgar Marxists is to fall into the metaphysical trap of treating Marxist concepts as categories and not social relationships. We have human rights not thanks to some innate spark or divine soul which makes us distinct from the rest of nature, but because we’re utterly reliant on making claims on each other in order to satisfy those material conditions of life which make us distinct as a species. We are treated as members of a certain race or ethnic group for sociological purposes not because of the colour of our skin or our place of birth, but because of how other people and social structures treat us based on those superficial and meaningless tags. We are coded as male or female not on arbitrary sexual characteristics observed at birth, but because others treat us in culturally-specific and largely arbitrary ways based - partly but not wholly - on those characteristics. Identity and performance cannot be separated entirely from one another since, as Marx wrote, “The phantoms formed in the human brain are also, necessarily, sublimates of their material life-process . . . .life is not determined by consciousness, but consciousness by life.

In this way, class position is, also, a fundamentally dialectical relationship. For Marx, a huge component of what makes us human is the observation that we must produce those things we need to satisfy our material needs, and that the act of production is in large part a social activity. The only way that human beings can grow sufficient food to feed ourselves, to refine the raw materials and assemble the finished goods which are characteristic of us as succesful, tool-using species is by entering into social relationships with others. And because production is a social activity, those who relate to production in different ways will be treated in different ways, and may come to see themselves as a members of different groups. Class position is not a matter of antagonism between rich and poor, determinable by some crude measure of wealth or income. It is about your material relationship to the means of production and your self-conscious identification of your social position in relation to production.

So, for instance, if you own your own home (no matter how expensive), then you are not a ‘capitalist’, since you are both the producer and consumer of housing services and you are not involved in any dialectical relationships with other people (partners and children notwithstanding). On the other hand, if a bank or landlord owns your home, then you have entered into dialectical relationship that contains within it the potential for class antagonism. Similarly, if you’re a retiree or pensioner who funds their retirement through taxes or savings generated through your labour (and with the caveat that those savings are stored in particular assets), then congratulations, you’re still a member of the working class even if your labouring days are long behind you. And yes, small business owner, you may ‘own’ your tools in the classical sense -your ‘means of production’ - but the odds are good that to get your business up and running you’ve taken loans or investments, you rent vehicles or properties form someone else, you rely on a technology platform you don’t own to advertise or to send you customers, or if you’re a franchisee, you might not own the intellectual property to your own goods and services. So your relationship to those who truly own the means of production is that of worker to capital.

Because society is complex, one’s class position is never binary; and the structures of modern capitalism often work to disguise or complicate those relationships as much as possible. Your class position may vary across different aspects of your life and relationships. A significant portion of private savings, for example, are not simple stored as cash or bonds but in the stock market, largely in the form of pension funds or passive investment vehicles. This puts private savers in a position of potential antagonism with the workers in those firms, because both groups make claims on the surplus value produced. The market works to obfuscate that antagonism, by distributing ownership widely (if you own stock in IBM, the odds of you interacting with an employee of that firm as an owner are miniscule) and by putting in place managerial intermediaries who exercise authority over workers within the firm on behalf of owners and thereby shield them from the hostility of the labouring class.

The professional-managerial class, a phenomenon largely unknown to the 19th century, therefore represents a very real phenomenon owing to the contradiction between their relationship to production and their self-conscious class position. The PMCs are almost entirely working class in a material sense - their salaries may be high, but they still survive based on labour rather than capital income - but whether out of ideological indoctrination or simple self interest, they identify their class position with that of capital and the capitalist system, acting as its enforcers, guardians, defenders and high-priests. That is true whether they are literal managers of firms, or members of the NGO industrial complex working to promote and advance human rights. Building a working-class movement that somehow includes or subordinates the PMCs is perhaps one of the defining challenges of the modern left - a task we cannot even begin to attempt until left-liberals and socialists start speaking a mutually intelligble language.

Book Release Announcement: "Evolutionary Politics: Socialism for Social Species"

Hello everyone,

I’m very pleased and excited to announce that my second book, “Evolutionary Politics: Socialism for Social Species”, will be published worldwide in late November 2020. The ebook version is already available for pre-order via Amazon and Apple Books - and the paperback will be available soon as well.

So what’s the book about?

The foundational myth of contemporary capitalism – the individual alone, in a state of nature – is just that: a myth. Both Darwin and early anarchists like Piotr Kropotkin understood that mutual aid lay at the heart of nature’s conquest of the earth. A rich tradition of evolutionary socialism and left-wing Darwinism has been forgotten and disparaged.

"Evolutionary Politics: Socialism for Social Species" applies the new science of cultural evolution to the modern world, showing that the rise of fascism, political extremism and tribalism can be best understood through an evolutionary lens. By demonstrating that humans are adapted for group life in symbolic communities, we can show how the myth of the rational actor has led economists, political scientists and policymakers to fundamentally misunderstand the human social world.

As we become ever more fractured and isolated from one another, "Evolutionary Politics: Socialism for Social Species" argues that not only is a better, more solidaristic world possible – it’s necessary if we are to survive as a species.

Contact me!

If you work in media, as a book reviewer, or if you’re an academic or activist working with game theory or cultural evolution, please reach out to me on Twitter at @ASkews2000 and I’d be happy to provide you a review copy in advance of the formal release.

And if you read the book and like it, why not drop a review on Amazon or on the book’s page on Goodreads? Every bit of feedback helps!

Book Review: “The Narrow Corridor” by Daron Acemoglu & James Robinson

I’m back from quarantine with another book review. Daron Acemoglu & Jame Robinson’s best-known book, “Why Nations Fail: The Origins of Power, Prosperity and Poverty” was a highly influential and persuasive defence of democracy, that I certainly found useful and informative in doing the research for my first book (“Politics for the New Dark Age: Staying Positive Amidst Disorder.”) Now they’re back with a follow-up, “The Narrow Corridor: States, Societies and the Fate of Liberty”, a 500-page behemoth that aims to perform the same service for liberalism. I regret to inform everyone, however, that “The Narrow Corridor” does not reach the same heights of the original, and in fact is a genuine slog to get through. Despite my genuine admiration for Acemoglu & Robinson’s academic work, I can’t recommend this book, and this blog will tell you why.

Acemoglu & Robinson’s central thesis is that the long-run success of states depends on the balance of power between the ‘state’ and ‘society’. If states are too strong, you end up with a Despotic Leviathan that is good for short-term growth but is brittle and unstable. If society is too strong, Leviathan is Absent and societies suffer under a pre-modern war of all against all. The ideal place to be, according to Acemoglu & Robinson, is the ‘narrow corridor’ where state and society are balanced, producing a ‘Shackled Leviathan’ that is able to grow state capacity and individual liberty simultaneously. The trick is to navigate into and stay in the narrow corridor (which one clever twitter user has already dubbed the ‘birth canal of liberalism’) against the centripetal forces pulling this delicate balance apart.

To their credit, Acemoglu & Robinson support their thin thesis with an extensive, and one might say exhaustive, set of case studies. And this is where the problems start. Although the authors’ selection of studies is broad and includes many non-Western cultures, the vast bulk of the book is little better than a potted history of civilisation, a tendency that gets worse in the second half where the authors cover so many unrelated topics (e.g. racial politics in the US, #metoo, the origins of Al Qaeda and the War on Terror, globalization, automation and the rise of the Nazis) that it covers none of them well. It falls into the trap of so much mediocre writing of mistaking description for analysis. So while their history of the world might be of interest to a first-year political science or economics student, it does not stand up as a serious work of scholarship.

Liberalism for dummies

From the reviews I’ve seen online, “The Narrow Corridor” is popular with neoliberals, even though the text itself ostensibly defends some version of a social democratic welfare state. The reason, I suspect, is its simplistic definition of what liberalism is and how it operate, and its almost Fukuyama-esque assumption that there is only a single stable evolutionary pathway that societies can take in the long-run. Acemoglu & Robinson are stuck in the tired dichotomy of Hobbes and Locke. In other words, the State is a despotic Leviathan that is necessary to provide order and prevent a war of all against all. The only way to constrain the state’s despotic tendencies is through individual rights, and some soft notion of ‘civil society’ that is never fully explained or developed.

Acemoglu & Robinson valorise the idea of Liberty, but their definition of it is deeply constrained. Throughout ‘The Narrow Corridor’, liberty is to be understood solely as ‘negative freedom’: restraints on what the state can and cannot do with regard to individuals and their property. The authors are curiously uninterested in the development of the individual, or the pursuit of happiness, in a way that might lead to demands for positive liberty. Instead, rights are a constraint on the despotic tendencies of the State, and individuals benefit from the growth in state capacity (so long as it does not become overmighty). One can easily see how such a worldview (“capitalism lifts people out of poverty”) may be sympathetic to neoliberalism’s core claim to rule.

But this is more than just an ideological objection. In “The Narrow Corridor” it is not individuals but the State which is the primary ontological entity. But what is the state, and where does it come from? Acemoglu & Robinson have a unfortunate and deliberate tendency to label everyone living outside a modern, Weberian nation-state as ‘stateless’, without any consideration of how governance emerges slowly and organically from within pre-existing structures. A State has police and bureaucrats, we are told: there is either the modern state form, fully formed and rational-legal in its orientation, or there is despotism. No other form of governance is worth consideration. As a result, Acemoglu & Robinson ignore the many forms of social organisation in history that were not states, and claims a great many things to be states which were not. Italian city-states which were legally part of the Holy Roman Empire and Muhammad’s early Islamic ummah are States; but the Islamic Caliphates and post-colonial governments in Africa and Latin America are not.

A dash of chauvinism

Acemoglu & Robinson rightly critique narrow works of history that focus solely on structural factors to explain the rise of civilization (looking at you, Jared Diamond), and prefer history that is messy and path-dependent. They claim this resurrects the role of ‘agency’ in history. But this is not the agency of individuals - there is no methodological individualism in “The Narrow Corridor”. The people who matter, the people with agency, are ‘state-builders’: law-givers, prophets and conquerers who stand astride world history as heroes. Despite their central thesis being one of constant tension between state and society, Acemoglu & Robinson specify almost no dynamic mechanisms in their theory: no classes, no divergence of interests, no means of production. States evolve over time, allegedly, yet in their cosmology they also emerge fully-formed from the hands of Great Men. After that, all that matters is that coalitions and inclusiveness are good and polarisation and social conflict are bad. Neoliberals in suits with technocratic cabinets are the ideal way to govern a state, forever.

Like all liberals, therefore, Acemoglu & Robinson propose a universalistic and trans-historical ideal of what constitutes a good state. The challenge they, and all liberals face, is to explain why this apparently successful social equilibrium is so difficult to achieve. It’s unclear what actually determines the balance of power between state and society: is it ideology, religion, economics, geography, or culture? At one point or another, all of these factors are thrown into the mix, but it’s hard to escape the impression that the authors have fallen into the trap of relying heavily on ‘cultural’ explanations for the success and failure of states.

In “The Narrow Corridor”, the archetypes of a successful Shackled Leviathan are ancient Athens, Italian city-states and the United States. What constrains the growth of state power, we are told, is the formation of society on the basis of free, smallholding peasant farmers. It’s an argument, I suppose. But while in some societies landowners are the fountainhead of liberty, in other societies are different times landowners are the chief centres of reaction and despotism. ‘Labour coercion’, we are told, undermines the growth of liberty, yet both ancient Athens and the United States were slave-holding societies. Privatisation is good until it isn’t. The lack of consistency is an inevitable result of the sheer number of stories being told and the lack of a coherent framework linking them together.

The other twinge of cultural chauvinism in “The Narrow Corridor” is that Acemoglu & Robinson really, really don’t like pre-modern forms of social organisation. In this book, any form of social governance which is not a Weberian rational-legal nation-state is by definition part of the ‘cage of norms’ which holds societies back, explains their failure to build states and undermines their economy. Peoples aren’t allowed to develop their own forms of self-governance based on kin networks, reciprocity, religion and custom - all that must be swept aside in the name of progress, most likely by some conquerer or law-giver with the public’s best interests at heart. Non-liberal cultures, we are told, oppress people and keep them impoverished. Better for everyone if social interactions are anonymised and conducted solely on the basis of self-interest.

In the final analysis, Acemoglu & Robinson’s account of the rise of Shackled Leviathans in the West is so simplistic it could come out of a Ben Shapiro book. Only in the West, we are told, did societies inherit the twin boons of Roman law and the ‘Germanic’ proto-democratic practice of tribal assemblies. It’s as if two millennia of war, feudalism, imperialism, colonialism and the Cold War never happened. Western political and economic institutions had a complex evolutionary history, and yet modern liberal States have the same cultural toolkit as the fifth century Franks (in much the same way, it must be said, that the Chinese Communist Party is ascribed the same cultural toolkit as the Qin Empire, 2500 years earlier). The glaring and obvious errors in many if their takes on European history makes the reader suspect that they’re picking and choosing their lessons from other parts of the world as well.

Bad Economists

Acemoglu & Robinson struggle the hardest, as most liberals do, when it comes to explaining the rise of China. They often come across as admiring and envious of the economic usefulness of the Despotic Leviathan and its capacity to organise short-term economic growth - although they are typically silent on the reasons for this (land redistribution, the suppression of labour and the concentration of capital might be among them). But they argue, weakly, that this is unsustainable and that China, under the rule of the Communist Party, can never pose a long-term challenge to the cultural West. Moreover, their unwillingness to theorise about civil society and social movements mean they have no prescriptions for the Chinese people to get out of this perceived trap.

Innovation, we are told, requires creativity and creativity requires liberty. That’s a hell of a claim, but it constitutes the sum total of their argument for the inferiority of despotism. At various points, we are told that government regulation of any kind is no different from despotism, and that free markets are the only road out of poverty. No form of social organisation that is not universal liberalism can deliver sustainable improvements in quality of life. But this is, empirically not true. Any even in the liberal West, States had a long history of despotic growth behind them before they became philosophically modern.

Conclusion

“The Narrow Corridor: States, Societies and the Fate of Liberty” is a book by liberals for liberals. It won’t convince anyone else of its central claims, and the longer the book goes on the more unfocused and self-defeating it becomes. Acemoglu & Robinson wanted to write a book about everything and ended up writing a book about nothing. No matter how extensively sourced or research, the authors offers no guidance to the future or wisdom about the past that one could not pick up from reading newspaper columns. A pity.

Book Reviews: “The Dream of Reason” & “The Dream of Enlightenment” by Anthony Gottlieb

Having finished writing my second book (tentatively title “Evolutionary Politics” and due to be published later this year, stay tuned), I’ve shifted my reading habits away from theoretical biology and radical theory to lighter and more mainstream pastures. So while in self-isolation this last few weeks (hello, Disaster Socialism), I’ve had the pleasure to read the first two volumes in Anthony Gottlieb’s history of Western Philosophy, “The Dream of Reason” (first published in 2000) & “The Dream of Enlightenment” (first published in 2016). Gottlieb, a former editor of The Economist, is a superb writer and his prose is light, economical and easy to parse. For anyone looking for a high-quality introduction to the field, I can highly recommend these books.

They are, however, very much histories of Western philosophy of the ‘dead white man’ variety. Gottleib apes Hegel (who devoted 800 pages to the ancient Greeks in his history of philosophy and 400 pages to the moderns) in his choice of subjects. The first volume, “The Dream of Reason” is less a history of philosophy up ‘to the Renaissance’ as advertised and more an introduction to Greek thought, with the majority of its time spent on the giants of Socrates, Plato and Aristotle. The second, “The Dream of Enlightenment” covers the pre-modern philosophers from Descartes to Hume, and a third volume covering Kant and beyond is reportedly on its way. Gottlieb combines brief biographical sketches of each thinker, to put them in their social context, with an in-depth discussion of two or three of their main philosophical arguments. Each subject is well-described, but the total absence of women or any thinker from outside Western Europe is glaring.

That said, Gottlieb is on the whole a fair and impartial biographer. He has little to say about the preservation and development of Plato’s and Aristotle’s thought by early Christian and Muslim philosophers, but at least the key figures are name-checked. Gottlieb is definitely a little too fond of Plato and Leibniz (both of whom he describes as geniuses despite their odd beliefs), and too critical of the Greek Heraclitus, and the French philosophes such as Voltaire and Rousseau. He prosecutes some of the ingrained prejudices of a liberal philosophical education, notably an rejection of moral relativism, a defense of free will and scepticism of a probabilistic universe, but these are generally minor digressions from the flow of his story-telling and easily forgivable.

A bunch of WEIRD-os.

Gottlieb’s biographical sketches demonstrate a point that perhaps the publishers who selected his book titles might like to disguise: very few of the heroes of the Western canon had a firm grasp on what Reason or the Enlightenment even were. The degree to which these founders of Western philosophy constituted a collections of weirdos, prophets and sages cannot be underestimated. Very few participated in formal education or empirical research, and most spent their time focused on questions of what we might think of today as theology and mysticism. Gottlieb notes how much of later Christian thought is infused with the mysticism of earlier Greek thinkers such as the numerology of the Pythagoreans, the Orphic belief in souls and Plato’s music of the spheres.

Descartes and Leibniz were also very much of this mould. Descartes, of course, is largely responsible for the metaphysical tendency in Western thinking that sees the mind and body as separate entities; two centuries later, Leibniz constructed an elaborate system of ‘monads’ in which material entities are merely imperfect reflections of abstracted pure entities. For these thinkers, Ideas were not only real entities but in some way more real than the material world which could be observed, sensed and experienced. Reason was not merely a tool, but a fragment of divinity that provided the only source of True knowledge, including about moral and ethical subjects. In these terms, many of Gottlieb’s subjects were effectively panpsychics - an equivalently absurd modern revival of such beliefs. In contrast, empiricists such as Democritus, Epicurus and Hume come across as eminently sensible.

Never go full Euclid

Gottlieb’s heroes are not the pragmatists who looked at human society with a sceptical eye, but proto-scientists such as Euclid, Galileo and Newton, and to a lesser extent Aristotle - whose system of syllogistic logic and biological investigations get a generous treatment. Gottlieb often comes across in awe of the power of the scientific method to produce knowledge that is both true and useful. But unlike many modern rationalists (“With a Capital-R”), he is cautious - or sensible - enough to recognise that a full embrace of scepticism would make some of the cultural and ethnical assumptions of Western philosophy untenable. Even though Descartes “I think, therefore I am” forms part of a system of mystical nonsense that is no longer explicit, we still rely on it to know anything at all.

Many of Gottlieb’s pre-modern subjects were obsessed with geometry, logic and the potential of the new ‘mechanical’ sciences (in much that same way of some modern analytic philosophers) - and he is fond of calling out the flaws of treating all knowledge this way. The ‘great’ philosophers tend to be such committed synthesisers of ideas that they embraced conclusions that appear absurd, monstrous or unintelligible. This includes Hobbes and Locke, two figures whom modern students of social science are most likely to know from their political philosophy. Hobbes was so committed to materialism that he believed, like the ancient Greeks Democritus and Epicurus, in a material God. And as anyone who has read Locke knows, his prose is so dense with definitions and exceptions that his work is less theory and more encyclopaedia. Despite their later reputation as the originators of modern liberalism and the social contract, both men were thoroughgoing authoritarians - as many men who think think highly of their own abilities tend to be.

The philosopher I personally enjoyed reading about the most was the thinker I had previously known the least - Baruch Spinoza. Spinoza’s reputation as a mystic is well deserved, but he was certainly less conventionally devout than Hobbes, Leibniz or Newton. It is a mistake, says Spinoza, to think of laws of nature - be their divine, philosophical or mathematical - in the same way as human laws. To note patterns in nature is not to infer a patriarchal law-giver, but this is just what modern psychologists would label an agency bias. Natural laws cannot be otherwise than as they are - they are descriptive, not prescriptive. Nothing, therefore, could be considered good or evil, sacred or profane other than in the human mind.

Spinoza was a European Jew, and one of the few uncritical supporters of liberal democracy in pre-nineteenth century philosophy. Positive traits and behaviours tended to increase the happiness of individuals and societies, but they are merely guideposts, not divine commands. For Spinoza, the mind and the body were one, and the body was subject to natural laws of cause and effect. Human beings are free to the extent that they can sometimes - but not always - understand the constraints imposed on them by natural laws. Spinoza was therefore something of a modern Stoic, resigned to the study of a world that was difficult, if not impossible to change.

Conclusion

For all our modern sophistication, much of modern Western philosophy is built upon a foundation that was first fixed in place more than 2500 years ago. What is remarkable in reading Gottlieb, quite frankly, is how little the pre-Enlightenment philosophers added to the diversity of opinions held by the ancient Greeks. For all their modernity, they were human beings just the same and ran up against the same limits to their imagination. The value of intellectual histories such as these therefore lies not in parsing how the ancients answered the big questions, but the way in which they highlight that some questions can never have satisfactory answers at all.

Sex is real. So is gender. The anatomy of propaganda.

I’ve tried to resist entering ‘the discourse‘ when it comes to analysing whether famed author JK Rowling is a TERF - a ‘trans exclusionary radical feminist’. For the record, Rowling’s actions suggest those of a TERF. Kat Blaque’s video embedded below addresses this better than I ever could:

Instead, I want to turn a critical eye to one element of Rowling’s now-infamous January tweet about a UK employment discrimination case that can teach us a useful lesson about how propanganda works.

Sex essentialism 101
I’m not going to go over all the myriad ways Rowling’s tweet oversimplifies and misrepresents the details of Maya Forstater’s failed legal challenge - the full text is available here and I recommend everyone take the time to read it. This was clearly a test case intended to set a legal precedent, and it fell over at the very first hurdle. Instead I want to focus on the line ‘sex is real’ because it’s a slick and in my opinion powerful bit of disinformation. The idea that gender critical feminists - and from hereon out I will try to use their preferred terminology - are simply defending the empirical proposition that ‘sex is real’ (and are not just, say, disguising anti-trans bigotry) is likely to become an enduring feature in this little culture war.

The phrasing demonstrates how propaganda can simultaneously set up a straw man about the position of so-called ‘gender theorists’, while obscuring the true position of the sex essentialists. No one of any consequences who supports trans rights says that sex isn’t real. The default position - accepted by academics, activists and, I would dare to add, broadly understood by the lay public - is that sex and gender refer to two separate English-language concepts and that which one to use to depends on the context. Gender typically refers to socially-constructed rules, norms and expectations which attach to categories of people on the basis of their behaviour and appearance. Sex, on the other hand, refers to bimodally distributed clusters of biological traits which are usually - but far from exclusively - linked in some way to reproductive function. It’s not that sex isn’t real, it just that it isn’t meaningful in many social contexts. When I listen to or read the works of trans people, they constantly and repeatedly emphasise that they are keenly aware of the ‘reality’ of biological sex. For many, though not all, trans and non-binary people, this reality is the cause of significant distress and their experiences are to a significant degree shaped by the effort it takes to manage the incongruence between their sex characteristics and gender identity.

Here’s the thing. The true position of gender critical feminists is in fact that gender isn’t real. That’s what they won’t - or can’t - admit, because it’s so extreme. They either believe that a social construction can’t be ‘real’ (at all!); or that any incongruence between sex and gender is the result of mental disorders deserving of sympathy, but not respect; or that the only relevant social category in (almost) all circumstances is sex. Either way, references to a person’s gender in ordinary English usage can refer to their biological sex and only their biological sex. As self-proclaimed critics of gender, they’re attempting to argue that socially constructed categories aren’t or shouldn’t be real, and that therefore attempting to modify or reform them in any way impossible and perverse.

If gender critical folks had their way, it would be linguistically impossible for anyone to identify with a gender other than the one they were assigned at birth, and their personal identification and social role would have no consequences. A trans woman would be treated by society for all intents are purposes as a man and a trans man as a woman. The medical, psychological and social evidence is that this position - long the historical default - causes harm to trans individuals, and enforces hierarchical and rigid notions about gender relations that end up also causing low-level anxiety for the vast majority of cis people. In the words of the British judge, it is a belief incompatible with the rights and dignity of other citizens.

By obfuscating their true position, gender critical feminists are attempting to hide the absolutism inherent in their nugatory beliefs. They’re sex essentialists in exactly the same way that self-proclaimed hereditarians are ‘race essentialists’ and the Stalinist/nazbol crowd are ‘class essentialists’. It’s a neat dogwhistle, because the lay reader (perhaps including JK Rowling?) is unlikely to recognise the trick being played on them. And it’s also a perverse bit of psychological projection, because they end up portraying their opponents - not themselves - as the defenders of an indefensible, unscientific position.

When does sex matter?

The essence of any good faith debate over the relevance of sex and gender centres around identifying the contexts in which each system of categorisation is most relevant. The progressive position, which I hold, is that for most social purposes gender is the most relevant categorisation, and that therefore there is wide scope for this system to be critiqued, challenged and reformed - or even abolished if we chose to. The reactionary position - shared by conservatives and gender critical feminists alike - is that sex is the most relevant categorisation more often than not, and that as a result that options of critique, challenge and reform are limited. Instead, (cis-) women must organise on the basis of sex in order to achieve social power and status equal to (cis-)men.

The first, and far and away most significant, context in which sex is the most relevant category is when it comes to health and medical treatment. A trans man may need to see a gynaecologist, and trans women may need to check for prostate cancer. Many diseases and health conditions affect sex characteristics differently, and it is in everyone’s self-interest that trans individuals, though socially and culturally of their chosen gender, receive medical treatment and advice best suited to the biological characteristics they actually possess. A menopausal cis woman, an intersex individual and a trans person may all require hormone treatment. In this way, “Good morning ma’am, have you experienced any discomfort in your penis?” is a perfectly logical English construction.

Secondly, we should recognise that romantic and sexual attraction is built in complicated ways on both sex and gender. Most people describe being attracted to some weighted combination of social performance and sexual characteristics, and some people are highly attracted to combinations of traits that are uncommon or transgressive. Some people may be highly motivated by the opportunity to reproduce and limit their choice of partners to those they can produce viable offspring with - ending relationships with infertile partners who they are otherwise attracted to. Some may be attracted to a person of the opposite gender but draw the line at same-sex genitals. But others may be totally comfortable with a feminine penis or male vagina. Many people will believe that what matters most is chemistry, personality or some other abstract quality. Since every adult human is entitled to full and absolute autonomy in their choice of partner - and to interfere with that choice is a crime - then people for whom some arbitrary sexual characteristic is a deal-breaker will always be able to act on those desires with any adult human who’d have them! Plenty of people have sexual desires that are considered socially questionable in some form or another.

Finally, we come to the vexed issue of sports. Sport is segregated in the interest of an abstract social goal of ‘fairness’. Sex and gender are merely being used as proxy variables for this goal. Defining what does, and does not, constitute an unfair competitive advantage is a complicated sociological question and by a process of trial-and-error most societies with professional athletics have prohibited a variety of chemical interventions while allowing unlimited funds to be spent on training, facilities and athlete development. Whether sex or gender, both or neither, are relevant to fair competition is as yet an open question. One trans athlete may outperform a cis person, but how much of that advantage is due to their biochemistry and how much is due to the social encouragement and development opportunities they might have received pre-transition? The burden of evidence is heavy, given both the statistically tiny number of trans athletes and the general physical exceptionalism of most athletes. Even if trans women were shown to have longer bones and wider shoulders than cis women on average, we would have no statistical reason to believe this difference would also exist among professional athletes. It’s also hard to avoid the impression of racial bias in these discussions, as many of the most exceptional trans- and intersex athletes (including notably Caster Semeya) have been non-caucasian.

The most plausible resolution to me right now seems to be a convergence on testosterone standards (in some sports) under which both trans- and cis- women can compete fairly, while excluding most cis-men, doping (cheating) athletes and athletes with rare medical conditions that might give them an unfair advantage. The widespread availability of hormone treatments also means any excessive innate biochemical advantage can be treated and reversed, if desired. Such tests would be simple for professional sports to apply, while amateur sports (where widespread blood testing might be infeasible) could continue to rely on gender as a low-cost proxy.

Gender rules

Once we accept the proposition that ‘gender is real’, we can subject it to serious criticism and debate. Many people - both cis and trans - are at ease with their gender roles; others think gender hierarchies should be deconstructed and rebuilt in more fluid or egalitarian ways; others are simply gender abolitionists, believing that all social norms, rules and behaviours based on stereotyped characteristics should be abolished entirely. All of these arguments and propositions are prima facie valid, because social structures can be remade by social beings however we’re able. Sex essentialists would take all these options from us, because they reduce behaviour to fixed biological traits that cannot be changed.

Nowhere is the debate between sex essentialists and gender realists less productive than when it comes to ‘women’s spaces’ such as bathrooms, refuges and prisons. The radical argument that everyone with a penis poses a threat to everyone with a vagina at all times makes sense within the gender critical framework, but appears puritanical and impractical as a guide to public policy to most people. On the other hand, gender realists argue that violence against women is a product of patriarchy - toxic socialisation which causes male-identified individuals to feel entitled to have access to or control women’s bodies. Whenever people in womens’ spaces - either cis or trans - are identified as predators then those individuals should be treated as the criminals they are, and sanctioned on the basis of their behaviour, not their identity or gender performance.

These are sometimes difficult questions. But when lay people appear uncertain or uncomfortable about these issues, and become susceptible to gender critical propaganda, it’s likely not because their instinctive beliefs about sex and gender are being called into question. It’s because they don’t know - and likely have never even thought before - about how those beliefs should apply in particular edge cases. That’s totally normal. But the propagandandist exploits that ambiguity and uncertainty to drive a wedge between people and their beliefs, whereas the activist is there to help and guide the public through unfamiliar terrain.